The Precautionary Principle A technical and economic perspective
|
According to Mr Pedersen what is needed in order to be able to use the principles is, first of all, factual knowledge focused on giving priority by way of the economic management instruments. Developments must lead to obtaining greater knowledge and better methods with which to reduce to the inadequate knowledge of cost-benefit analyses. He concluded his talk by recommending that priority be given to fundamental research in environmental economy.
Ib Knudsen
Institute director, Institute for Food Safety and Toxicology
When this question was first put to me, I thought that it was easily answered with a
yes. We scientists do know something about biology, about the test methods and
the practices that are used in risk assessment. On the other hand it says defining
risks, and that can be something completely different, namely the question of
whether a risk is acceptable. So I concluded that the answer could also be no.
Thus, today, my point of departure is yes and no.
As I was a little unsure of what the precautionary principle actually was, I had to begin
by searching for some literature on the subject. As it turned out the concept originated
in West Germany where the vorsorge principle was used. It was entered into German
legislation in 1976 accompanied by the following explanation. An environmental
policy is incomplete if it only deals with the great dangers and eliminates damage that
has already been inflicted. Preventive environmental policy also requires that
natures resources are protected and that they are used cautiously.
As mentioned, the precautionary principle was called the Vorsorge-Prinzip in Germany which
does not really mean precaution but care. Thus the starting point
is care for the environment. According to my literary source this led to quite a bit of
confusion when the Germans returned home to tell of what they had learnt at the first
conference on The precautionary principle that had to be translated back into the German
Vorsorge-Prinzip. I am not aware of what term is currently in use in Germany,
but the example clearly illustrates the problems that arise within a multilingual field
when understanding just exactly what we are talking about.
The principle then found its way to the second conference on the Protection of the North
Sea. Here, the following words were used to describe it. It has to be accepted that
in order to protect the North Sea against the possible harmful effects of the most
hazardous substances, a precautionary attitude must prevail which can lead to actions such
as checking the discharge of such substances before a connection between the cause and
damage done is proven based on absolute scientific fact.
This has been continued in many other connections and, as those who have spoken here today
before me have said, the precautionary principle has now been applied many times. There
has not been a term for it as such earlier, but the basic concept was applied (see fig.1).
In the same book, The precautionary principle and International Law by D. Freestone and E.
Hey (eds.) (Kluwer Law Inter-national, The Netherlands, 1996), it was emphasised that the
term was already used in the States in 1972 in connection with the discharge of substances
in the environment, based on the notion that the discharge of substances is bad and should
be reduced to the limits of available technology.
In actual fact the principle was also used in whaling. There was some uncertainty whether
whaling could safely continue. Once there was proof that it could not, it would be too
late to take any action as the whales would already be extinct.
Fig.1
Early and other uses of the precautionary principle before the principle was
officially formulated
|
![]() | 1) If nothing is done to regulate matters non-ignorable damage can occur. |
![]() | 2) There is insufficient knowledge regarding the connection between cause and effect. |
![]() | 3) In the two circumstances mentioned in the above, to not regulate is not justifiable. |
In reality this is also the order in which things are done. What often happens is that
something is suspected of entailing a risk of some sort. Once suspicion has been aroused,
scientists are approached and asked whether they know anything about it. Something is
often known, but there is no scientific evidence of a connection. In such cases the
decision can be to introduce legislation so as to play it safe.
Dr H. Reichenbach, Directorate General XXIV, which is the EUs consumer directorate,
states clearly: "The precautionary principle must be based on science. Otherwise it
is impossible to use". The means that science is the central axle that everyone uses
as a frame of reference when decisions are to be made.
The precautionary principle can be used in risk management - what Erik Lindegaard called
risk control. The word control makes it sound as if someone is in charge, and
that is rarely the case - this is why management is better. The precautionary
principle can be used when, in a given situation, we do not have a quantitative risk
assessment, when we are unsure of the scientific data, and when science still can not
offer a certain answer that can shed light on what has been called into question based on
the current methods.
In the Paris Commission it was established that it can be necessary to act when science
presumes there is a connection, even though there is no definitive proof of such a
connection.
The precautionary principle raises two questions:
Firstly: Which risk level justifies application of the precautionary principle? Is it when
the risks are huge or when the risks are unacceptable? I will not try to answer these
questions here, but I will say that what we must begin with are risk levels that seem to
be acceptable so as to have some sort of scale of comparison.
At the same time we must acknowledge that we, as scientists, can not see further that the
eye and thought and instrument can reach. There will always be discoveries tomorrow that
we know nothing of today. This is one of the things that could be behind a desire to use
the precautionary principle. Scientific assessment will be based on the so called
weight-of-evidence principle and the available data. When we have all the data, some data
will show that a substance is carcinogenic in some animal tests but not in others, and
that it functions in some mutagenic test systems but not in others. Then we carry out a
complete assessment of these data - weight-of-evidence - and a group of can experts make a
decision. However, I am sure that a different group of experts would, based on the same
data, find that they should be assessed differently. This can lead to managements
desire to include the precautionary principle.
The second question is which actions based on precaution are reasonable? Should preventive
measures be introduced? Should there be a switch to the best possible technology or a
clean production, and should alternative possibilities be considered? The examples we have
been presented with today reflect all types of activity. Erik Lindegaard mentioned the
example of BAM that has not been banned, but it is being considered whether some
preventive action and cleaner production should be introduced. About food additives it can
be said that preventive actions are being introduced by limiting the amount used as seen
in the positive list, but it is not forbidden to use them. This is actually also the case
for pesticides.
These considerations take place in a larger context. The structure of risk analysis is
based on three elements (see fig. 2):
1) Risk assessment
2) Risk management
3) Risk communication
Risk assessment consists of a) assessment of hazards, b) characterisation of hazards,
c) assessment of exposure, d) risk characterisation. It is in this phase that the experts,
with the aid of various safety factors and mathematical models, can calculate an
acceptable or tolerable daily intake.
Risk management: The decision itself concerning what the safety factor should be is
actually an element of the risk management. It here that it is decided whether to use a
standard safety factor of 100, an extra safety factor for children and so on. It is a
decision based on politics. In the same phase the safety related problems that are to be
subjected to a risk assessment are identified. The experts do not begin to assess
something unless they have been instructed to do so - they do not have the resources to do
this! In the risk-evaluation phase the problem is described and given a priority with
regard to the risk assessment, and then a risk-assessment tactic is chosen. This is often
done in collaboration with the experts. Then the actual risk assessment is put into action
and finally the result of this is managed. The latter takes place without consulting the
experts. The other phases in risk management involve possibilities for management,
implementation of management, and finally a total view assessment, that is installation
and evaluation.
Fig. 3
Important issues in the interface between risk assessment and
risk management (From S. Slorach, 1998)
|
Risk communication: In the third element it is crucial to communicate with consumers,
producers and other interested parties. This communication should be clear, open and
interactive. Consultations should preferably take place and all parties should be informed
of what has been planned before the procedures are actually implemented.
Thus there are many elements that have to fall into place in the process. Not all of it
has been settled at the present time - there are still some things that are under
discussion. Slorach from the Swedish Food and Nutrition Institute has set up a long list
(see fig. 3). There should be more consultation about risk analysis and assessment,
management and communication. There is no consensus of opinion in this matter.
A risk assessment policy should be established as part of the risk-management process,
that is, what it is one wishes to assess, because some things are not assessed at all at
the moment. Should we also assess biological control agents? It is being done now, but
this is a fairly recent measure. The focus has primarily been on chemical agents. It is
typical of a risk-assessment policy that some areas are left alone and some are subjected
to regulation.
Fig. 4
Also, scientific assessment must be distinguished from value judgements. That people find
some things more important than others - for example mad-cow disease or traffic - must be
distinguished from the actual scientific assessment.
The stating of scientific uncertainty - default assumption - in risk assessment and
application of the precautionary principle in risk management, are two different stages in
the process - once again I completely disagree with Erik Lindegaard. The precautionary
principle is definitely an instrument to be used in risk management and it is inextricably
bound to those tasks that the EPA must deal with. This does not mean that science can not
take part in the discussion, but that the decision concerns something far greater than
risk assessment. This is also the case when considering such tasks as establishing
reasonable safety levels, defining what the Acceptable Daily Intake means, and management
of carcinogenic substances.
Finally, the total view must not be forgotten, this not only concerns risks or advantages,
but also a complete assessment of the advantages, disadvantages and acceptance. In the
assessment of acceptance, the publics attitude regarding whether the risk in
question is especially unacceptable must be taken into consideration whether or not the
risk is deemed quantitative in the eyes of science.
A commission appointed by the President of the United States and the American Congress
wrote a report in 1997 in which guidelines for risk management of environmental cases are
laid down. A lot is done to present a cyclic process (see fig. 4). First of all, the
problem and the context in which it appears must be identified. Then, the risks involved
are analysed and the possibilities for managing these risks are examined more closely, a
decision is made and carried out, and, finally, the result is evaluated. This evaluation
can lead to repetition of the process in order to improve the result. Interested parties
should be involved in all of these decisions. The industrialist, the worker, the consumer,
in short all stakeholders or interested parties should be involved in an ongoing
discussion of the problem. This is probably what we have neglected most in Europe.
The American report calls attention to the advantages of involving all interested parties:
The EPA has asked me to answer what level of scientific knowledge or substantiated
suspicion should lead to taking the Principle into use. The examples I mentioned show the
types of legislation that repeatedly apply the precautionary principle as a basic
principle without actually mentioning it.
The examples illustrate that the application of the precautionary principle is based on
incredibly varied scientific standards. Other values play a very important part, namely
what the general public thinks and therefore what politicians think. This again influences
what the authorities think and, finally, the producers, workers, etc.
influence is not to be forgotten either.
However, the decisive factor in the application of the precautionary principle is
nevertheless objective scientific data. An excellent example of this are oestrogen-like
substances. Some notions concerning possible problems with these substances appeared in
scientific literature. The EPA began to investigate the matter and this led to the
production of quite a lengthy scientific report, the first of its kind, which was later
published in an international scientific journal.
This report presented scientific state-of-the-art knowledge. It illustrated how little we
know about these substances and that we do not even have methods with which to establish
how we should assess them. Scientists even managed to disagree on whether they affected
the quality of semen or not. Questions were raised whether the data could even be seen to
be a true reflection of reality.
But the debate did lead to society, in the guise of the EPA, applying the precautionary
principle. A great deal of research was begun in the area, and as an initiative this
research was given prominence - there was a great deal of focus on obtaining as much
knowledge of the presumed oestrogen-like effect of these substances as possible. So, in
this situation manifestation of the precautionary principle was the implementation of
research programmes.
Philippe Grandjean, Odense University:
To what extent are the uncertainties that you have presented actually considered
when presenting a risk assessment - be it the Veterinary and Food Control Service, the EPA
or other expert authorities that are responsible for these things?
Do you think that the uncertainties are presented clearly enough, or do the authorities
take them into consideration in a concealed manner and weigh the problems themselves so
that the democratic processes that you refer to do not actually take place?
Ib Knudsen:
In the 60s, a group of experts would get together in a room and look at the
available data concerning pesticides, etc. They would stay in the room until smoke would
come out of the chimney in the form of a number, and that was the number. In the 70s and
80s there has been an increasing desire amongst all other possible interested parties to
know just how the experts arrived at this number. It is a process still in action and it
still has not reached its conclusion. Philippe Grandjean can find numerous examples in the
last 20 years of Danish risk assessment of how difficult it is to find the documents that
were used, and the reasoning that these numbers are based on. This is not because the
experts do not want to be checked up on, but because it simply was not done at the time.
Today the public can read about the scientific basis of these decision in a series of
reports published by the EPA. Correspondingly, risk assessments from scientific committees
in the EU are published as reports on the Internet. Today, things are so advanced that all
reports and decisions made are available on the Internet no later that three weeks after
we have held the meeting, so that anyone can see what we have decided.
In the mad-cow disease case we also prepared a draft assessment of meat and bone meal,
which we published because we were not sure that we, in the group which had been appointed
to assess the question, knew enough about how meat and bone meal are produced, and how to
ensure that the prions which cause BSE were not in the products. We put this draft on the
net and invited everyone to comment on it within a period of three weeks. At the same time
we sent the draft to some people we felt might have a particular interest in the matter.
Within three weeks we had received 24 comments of which many included elements that we
could include in our assessment and thus contributed to improving the final assessment.
I think this is something we will see more and more of. In the States they have a Federal
Register. The FDAs and EPAs proposals for assessment and their attitudes
towards various issues are published in the Federal Register and have been so for the past
20-30 years. This has made it possible for anyone to comment on the issues, and everyone
receives an answer, even though not all opinions are taken into consideration. This
process is just getting started in Europe and it is a process that we must all learn to
work with and try to make positive use of.
I think it is safe to say that none of us have fully mastered it yet, but we are trying as
best we can to answer all the questions we receive. It will be the trend in our
information society in that everything should be made accessible, it should be seen on TV,
heard on the radio, and be available on the net. Yes, that will be the future.
Peter Skov, Confederation of Danish Industries:
You began by saying both yes and no, but I think you
managed to express some views about risk analysis and risk conditions. I agree with, and
am a little surprised, that Erik Lindegaard thinks that the precautionary principle is an
element in risk assessment or risk analysis.
However, my question concerns something completely different. You mentioned two reports,
one from the Swedish Food and Nutrition Institute and one from the States. I understood it
as if they were in favour of opening the system up a bit, and you touched upon that
towards the end of your talk. If one considers the debate in Denmark concerning risk and
risk conditions, do you have any idea as to how such a debate and openness could be
systematised?
Ib Knudsen:
I have mentioned the EPAs reports that include different risk assessments.
In the Veterinary and Food Control Service we also publish a series of reports. Finally,
the entire EU system is gradually looking forward to more openness.
I will take this opportunity to show you one of the overheads I did not use earlier (fig.
5). In connection with the case about mad-cow disease, where both the Commission and the
EU lost consumer confidence, the scientific committees that gave advice on these matters
were all brought together in the consumer directorate , DG 24, comprising 140 experts in
nine committees.
The advice they offered the Commission was in the form of opinions which were available to
the public and could be criticised, attacked and so on. In Denmark we must discuss the
many different modes of openness and how to use them in practice.
Peter Skov:
I would like to add something to my initial question. With all due respect, the
EPAs publications regarding risk assessment will probably never make it to the
best-seller list. When we talk of risk communication how will the basics in risk
assessment be communicated comprehensively to the public?
It may seem a little naive, but if we consider your presentation of the American way, the
first step was to call attention to the problem, the next step was an assessment and
finally there was some form of action. This is a fairly simple procedure, but I know in
fact it is not simple no matter how it is done. At some point there must be some input on
how to see, assess and lay down regulations. The EPAs risk assessments are quite
advanced technical reading, and it is my judgement that they are not exactly the
medias, nor politicians, most quoted sources of information.
Ib Knudsen:
The weekly terror stories shown on TV actually deal with this problem. Here, we
see a great many Danish experts trying to communicate some things more or less
successfully, depending on what your personal opinion to each case is.
Television plays a very important part, but, other than the formal risk-management
process, I think the authorities have to be better at involving many interested parties,
and releasing questions for the general public to consider, before actually reaching an
administrative decision. The Internet and e-mail have enabled the quick dispatch of
assessments and proposals to a great number of people who can then express their opinions
regarding the matter, thus provoking debate. I think that is the way to go about it.
Poul Harremoës
Professor in Environmental Technology at the Danish Technical University
Thank you for this opportunity to speak about the precautionary principle. It is exciting
that as a direct result of what has already been said I have obtained a reasonably clear
understanding of what is meant by the three last concepts, that is, preventive efforts,
intervention at source, and the polluter pays. On the other hand, I am relatively confused
about what is meant by the first concept; the precautionary principle. My point of
departure is therefore that confusion is greater than understanding in relation to this
principle.
If we talk to people on the street about what the precautionary principle is, we can
easily receive the banal reply that it is something to do with taking precautions. If we
talk to someone who is a little more in the know, they will say that it is something to do
with better protection of the environment and that, in fact, is quite a sensible reply. If
we ask the experts, the most frequent reply is that the precautionary principle is a
desire to shift the burden of proof from the complainant, who previously had to prove that
a given action was harmful, to the defendant, who must prove that the action is harmless,
that is a shift to the polluter. A shift of weight which I will take as my first point of
departure for closer analysis.
EU 1992: Principles
|
What does the principle say? The precautionary principle shifts the burden of proof:
|
Claim: The substance is harmful
|
Claim: The substance is harmless
|
I will discuss two instances at both ends of the scale. One involves a claim that the
substance is harmful. Now, we assume that we have fully clear criteria. Should there be a
ban or not? In this instance the burden of proof for the claim can be raised. In fact the
claim can be proven. If we conduct sufficient investigations, we can prove that the
criteria laid down have not been complied with. So the substance is harmful, and as a
result should be banned. It is immediately more complicated to raise the opposite burden
of proof: the substance is harmless. Harmlessness cannot be proven. There is
so much harm which can be caused, and so much harm to children, the weak, the elderly,
ecosystems, rare species, or similar we do not know about yet.
A claim of harmlessness can only be made likely by induction, which in scientific theory
means experience. I would like to offer an example of this, as it is certain that there
are several who are strangers to this view. In order to be sure that everyone understands,
I would like to refer to the philosopher Popper, who in 1972 wrote a book on philosophy
which gave an example. If you look at swans in Denmark you will see that they are white.
As a result of travelling in Denmark you could think that swans are white. You could
perhaps be tempted to claim that all swans are white. In order to test this hypothesis you
could go to Europe and onwards to America and Asia. You will still find confirmation of
the claim by induction, but in Australia there is an exception, for there are black swans.
The claim was wrong!
This is induction. It is not a result of deduction; it is a result of experience. In this
way the attractive statement of shifting the burden of proof suddenly stands in a
completely different light. Therefore, as a direct result of what has been said, I am of
the opinion that it is a question of confidence. It is showing likelihood, not proof.
Lawyers will possibly say circumstantial evidence.
Sufficiently appropriate procedures are in this way decisive factors in developing
confidence. My last claim is that in recent years there have been too many contradictions
which have broken down confidence. This is, in fact, the fundamental problem facing us. As
an example of how the precautionary principle can be interpreted, I have chosen a quote
from the North Sea Convention. Discharges of a substance which can lead to serious
damage should be limited as far as possible, even if there is no scientific evidence of a
connection between the discharge and its harmful effect on the environment.
We have heard this many times, but I would like to highlight the word
evidence. Now we are at the end of the scale where we can, in fact, produce
evidence, rather than the opposite end where we cannot. At this end of the scale, where we
can produce evidence, we do not need to. That is, at both ends of the scale it is only
necessary to show likelihood as a basis for the decisions we are talking about. Therefore
the precautionary principle is not a mantra which can be called upon, a deus ex machina
which can be called up as a magic potion to provide a scientific absolute. It is a
consideration which builds on things, and not a fixed dimension which can be
called in or ignored at will. In this way I am entirely in agreement with Ib Knudsen in
that it is an overall principle which shifts attention but which has been there all the
time. We cannot have risk assessment without its presence as an overall principle, no
matter what the problem.
If we now are to follow this up with evidence, of which there is not much left, then what
is the consequence of shifting? It is that this shift makes it obvious that it is the
polluter who must make efforts to show that it is likely that a substance is harmless and
to create the desired confidence. This is not what is happening today, but can it be done?
As part of the competition here amongst those holding lectures, on who can
cite the precautionary principle furthest back in time, I will beat everyone by saying
that it has, in fact, applied for 150 years. This is an example of how the precautionary
principle has worked and still works. Over 150 years, water supplies have been made so
that we can open a tap and drink the water without becoming ill. And the Danish population
has confidence in this, despite the fact that now and then accidents happen, such as in
Uggerløse some years ago. This occurs when an engineering student did not pay attention
at the first tutorial on technical hygiene when it was said that a prerequisite for
uncontaminated water supplies is that there is always complete separation between dirty
and clean water, and this can sometimes not be the case.
Confidence
|
Declaration of Sustainable Development in the ECE, 1990 Quote: |
Showing likelihood
|
The precautionary principle - what is it then? All that is left to prove is: The polluter must demonstrate the likelihood of harmlessness and create the desired confidence. |
An old principle, but:
|
Risk of errors The precautionary principle should manifest itself as a demand to assess the uncertainty and consequences of possible errors. |
Assertion
|
However one looks at it, the decision is political - hopefully based on appropriate
information to aid in balancing.
Categories of error
|
If we measure the coliform index of water, the precautionary principle crops up again. It
starts the great hunt for where the bacteria came from. Until this is found we are unable
to drink the water without boiling it. This has worked satisfactorily for a 100 years,
even though everyone recognises that there is a risk. If you wish to expose yourselves to
this risk, then travel to Cairo, open the tap and take a slurp! Then the precautionary
principle is inverted. Today, some people who wish to save water, that it for
environmental reasons, will set up installations in buildings so that unpurified water
comes into close proximity with clean water with the undoubted increased risk that they
could come into contact with each other. When bodgers do this in their own home, the risk
is increased.
Now comes the interesting point. The people who make these installations expect the
authorities to prove the harmlessness of them. In my opinion, the precautionary principle
would say that they should do this themselves. This is an interesting point of view which
could possibly help the authorities to handle these idealists.
There is no doubt that with this example I have diluted the content of the precautionary
principle considerably. I would like to develop it by wording the principle in another
way. There is a risk of error.
The precautionary principle should manifest itself as a demand to assess uncertainty and
the consequences of possible error. I will do this by again addressing two assertions. The
assertion of harmlessness and the assertion that it is of harmful.
In both cases: What is the uncertainty, and what are the consequences of error?
In the first case, this is called the false negative, in the second the false positive. In
all situations it ends with a question of balancing the fact that we do not know things
well enough. This means that ultimately there must be a political decision and there are
examples of how earlier these political decisions took place behind closed doors. We heard
of white smoke as part of the process once the experts had finished bickering. During this
process, which I think the lawyer spoke about well, the decision is hopefully based on
very specific knowledge which can be provided by specialists, technology, science, and so
on.
After this I cannot help bringing up a number of categories of error. We must now analyse
explicitly what could happen if we made an error. We do not like admitting this, but like
gymnastics, it is healthy.
Let us start with determinism, which assumes that there is a crystal-clear connection
between the influence and the result. It is never found in practice, but is an ideal.
We can make a calculated risk which is that we know the uncertainty, we can quantify it,
and we have the statistical tools to treat it in an appropriate manner. This is a
well-established discipline which is also applied in risk analysis.
After this I talk about uncertainty. This is where we have identified the uncertainty, but
we have no data to quantify it. Therefore we must go over to a qualitative assessment of
how we will stay on the safe side.
From this we move straight on to ignorance. An example is the oestrogen-like effects which
no one knew of five years ago.
To be a little provocative, what will come up in the next ten years? It will clearly be a
problem which we will have difficulty in addressing, but which some will want us to make a
decision on.
It is even worse with unpredictability, and here I am not thinking of the weather
forecast, or chaos theory. We learn that we must consider many things in the future. The
question could be put, can we predict at all what will happen when under sustainability we
must consider the possible consequences for future generations? This can only
be done as an extrapolation of our own daily lives.
Imagine that someone at the turn of the century had to carry out actions which took
account of how we have turned out today, and do this on a basis that was known in the
1890s. There would be a great deal of guesswork, and I regard the two last factors -
ignorance and unpredictability - as fundamental in this problem. How can the precautionary
principle be applied when we do not even know what it is about, and can not predict social
conditions in 50 years?
In the European Environmental Agency we are working with this based on what is called the
D.P.S.I.R approach. Here we find our driving forces, that is our desires for well-being,
for example to drive a car, through pressure on the environment. What does this lead to in
our surroundings, that is, what impact does this have on us and ecosystems? Then there are
the responses which in society we arrange in the light of an objective based on criteria
and indicators with which we can intervene at all levels. Here is an established way to
view this which is reminiscent of life-cycle analysis, but which is based on
societys view, not on the manufacturers view of its product. About the
connection between measure, state, and impact, I will
say that one must add a certain measure of causality to the concept if it is to have any
meaning at all, and this has in fact been said already.
Balancing usefulness against damage. I dare make the assertion that people are well
acquainted with the likelihood of damage in many cases. Smoking has been mentioned, or
what about driving? I drove here in my car this morning. The risk of doing this in the
Copenhagen traffic is greater than anything else I expose myself to during the day. I
choose to drive despite this knowledge.
The other factor has already been mentioned by Erik Lindegaard. People react when
uncertainty is involuntary and usefulness is doubtful. I do not believe that people are as
stupid as specialists make them out to be.
The DPSIR approach to environmental management Criteria, indicators, targets Ultimate objectives Driving forces Responses Pressures, States, Impacts Physical, chemical, and biological cause-effect relationship Usefulness against damage People can be well acquainted with the likelihood of damage:
Usefulness against damage |
The example of pesticides and nitrates in groundwater has already been mentioned, and the
same applies to mad-cow disease. These things in my opinion also relate to the fact that
usefulness has something to do with agriculture which over produces at the same time as it
pollutes in order to become more efficient. People well realise this. In the case of
mad-cow disease, I am sure that most of the Danish population realise that the risk is
incredibly small. However, it is unacceptable when we hear that it applies to us because
cows must eat the corpses of other cows. I have a certain sympathy with this. Usefulness
and damage come into play when assessing the risk one wishes to expose oneself to.
Therefore, I will stick my neck out with the following statement of the criteria for
intervention:
Probable fear of serious and widespread damage which outweighs other social consequences
of intervention.
If you think that this is nebulous, then in my opinion it is a reflection of the changed
emphasis in the balance in a process where one cannot claim to have precise scientific
solutions. However, one can hopefully obtain data and information as a basis for this
balancing.
I have two things to say about risk analysis with which I would like to influence the
debate in a way which I hope does not sound too critical. One is that traditional risk
analysis is very reductionist. It must go into detail in order to be extrapolated to an
assessment. There is a need for wholes, I call them patterns, and we could discuss this
for a long time. The second thing I would like to say is that traditional risk analysis is
too esoteric. Ib Knudsen said a lot about this, and we agree that we must go this way.
Finally, for some time I have been renewing the precautionary principle because I think it
is nebulous. In the Scientific Committee in the European Environmental Agency, we have
gathered the best minds in Europe to outline a theoretical foundation. The objective is to
come up with a system which will contribute to the ultimate political balancing.
It is about a theoretical outline of examples from the past ten, twenty, perhaps 150 years
of how it has, in fact, worked, when it has gone wrong, and when it has been successful.
We have taken the initiative to arrange this, and if there is anyone who can give me some
good advice, I would like to hear it. We are arranging the first meeting in the autumn, so
there is still time to make a positive contribution.
Finally I would say that, in order to develop this at European level in the European
Environmental Agency, it would be exciting if we could form a Danish backing group, for
example with speakers from this hearing, so that there is input from Denmark as part of
this European analysis. I will gladly accept comments.
Peter Skov, the Danish Confederation of Industries
You said that there were not adequate appropriate procedures to create the
necessary confidence in the decisions which are made based on the precautionary principle.
However, before you further explain this, I would like to mention something which you
said, and try to justify it.
In your discussion of the burden of proof, you concluded that the polluter must show how
likely a result is. If it were true that in a court of law one could show how likely
ones claim were, I would agree with you that this is a simple solution to the
problem. However, the fact is that things must be solved by a political process, we have
agreed on this today. Politicians must make decisions, and when they consider our topic
today, they probably have the same confidence in the statements of industry about the
state of the environment and impacts on the environment as the public have. And I can say
that this is not especially great.
Therefore, politicians employ experts in authorities and they pay researchers. What is the
role in this debate of particularly the latter group, to which you belong, apart from
delivering profound works?
Poul Harremoës
Thank you for your confidence in our profound works! You ask first what basis I
have for stating that the procedures must be improved. This is purely inductive. There are
many conflicting examples of peoples political opinions and what they will tolerate.
We must join in helping risk analysis advance by making more analyses - and here I think
it is more the social aspects than the chemical and biological. This is my reaction in
reductionist practise.
The report which was issued three years ago in England called Risk has two
concluding paragraphs. One is a traditional risk analysis, and the other includes a social
element. Each wrote their report, and each made their interpretations with their own
specific scientific bases. They were never able to agree during committee work. Bridges
must be built between the two parts.
It is relatively rare to see a report from the Royal Society in England where the groups
so totally disagree. This made interesting reading, based solely on this view. My claim is
that we must help to get this going by widening each horizon, but this is purely
inductive. It is not deductive that this is the basis for saying there must be improved
procedures. It is simply by observing the effects over the last ten years. I do not know
how we should tackle this precisely, but the precautionary principle must play a part in
such a development, as well as inter-disciplinary co-operation.
With regard to the role of researchers, then Peter Gjørtlers words as a lawyer were
perfect. It is lawyers and courts which say this. It is not specialists who must make
political decisions.
Peter Skov
That is just what you should not be doing
Poul Harremoës
Yes, but I have a reason to say this, also through induction. Peter
Gjørtlers wording is entirely correct. Specialists offer, hopefully, the most
objective input they can, so that the political and administrative system have a basis for
finding a political balance which some specialists also like to contribute to, but which
they are neither qualified nor responsible to do. In this regard, for many years I have
said - and shocked many of my colleagues in doing so - that experts are dangerous.
Lone Johnsen, the Danish Society for the Conservation of Nature
I agree that, although we in Denmark, and especially at EU level, have taken many
initiatives, the current chemical legislation and regulations in Denmark have to a great
extent gone wrong. It is positive that this perception is not merely shared by the green
organisations, but is also discussed in the Council of Ministers and in the Commission.
Three weeks ago there was a meeting of Ministers of the Environment where it became clear
that the Commission had already been asked to provide a draft for a new framework
directive on regulation of chemicals in the EU.
Further to what Peter Skov has said, this is at least proof that the chemical industry
must also look forward to a whole new ball game and the industry has perhaps
not done so well in this process up to now.
What would you emphasise in a new framework directive for the chemical area? You started
on something important that natural sciences and social sciences must be combined with a
view to operationalising this area further. Do you have some good examples that this has
already happened, or are we starting from scratch?
Poul Harremoës
I would like to answer that in two years time, as a result of the
initiative we have taken in the European Environmental Agency to make this analysis.
Furthermore, I am not so sure that we need more fine declarations on principles.
Rather, we need to interpret the principles which already exist, and apply them in a
practical and common-sense way, in accordance with the principles, so that we pave the way
for their administration. The problem is only at the level that we need support. Just as
environmental employees in a private company need support from the board. Things happen at
a lower level, but we can not get things done here unless there is support from above.
This is already happening in industry to an impressive extent.
Ole Vinther Christensen, GEUS
You talked a lot about the logical, the rational, and the irrational. In the
Ministry of Environment and Energy we have looked at media treatment of these things. I
share your observations about confidence. In certain areas we can see that the press are
irrational. It is very good that we, as engineers, make some rational procedures which are
published on the Internet. But, when we see that the media are irrational, I would like to
hear your comments on this situation, on how we can tackle the irrational elements, and,
if I may say so, how we can control them.
Poul Harremoës
You cannot control them. I think that I can briefly come up with an answer. By
beating them to the post in the long term. I can give a good example of this. I have taken
part in relationships between NGOs and stakeholders in Hong Kong, Sydney, and Auckland.
I will not speak further about Hong Kong and Sydney as the situations here were hopeless,
but I was very impressed in Auckland, New Zealand. In connection with extending a very
large sewage plant, relationships were developed to all stakeholders who had any interest
or desire at all to take part. These relationships were built up over many years.
This meant that no one was surprised that the press could not come up with any great
controversies. This was not possible, because those with an interest in the matter had
already been fully informed. It was extremely impressive co-operation, and I can recommend
anyone who is interested to take a trip to New Zealand. However, I would not recommend
Australia, and certainly not Hong Kong.
I would claim that here in Denmark we are nowhere near. If we suggested to the Lynette
sewage works, which I have close contact to, that we should work with the stakeholders for
three years in order to build up such relationships, they will shake their heads and say,
" this is not part of our normal practice". In this regard we are ahead of
Australia and Hong Kong, but far behind New Zealand.
Hans Sanderson:
What changes in recognised theories in natural and technical sciences are
necessary in order that we may achieve these sustainable solutions, and in order that
ignorance and unpredictability can become relevant subjects in a scientific debate, and
not subjects to be avoided all the time? In this way integration of natural and social
sciences would be achieved, instead of merely parallel co-operation. I believe this is
vital if we are to meet these challenges within risk assessment and regulation.
Poul Harremoës
This question is so interesting, that unfortunately I have no answer to it, just
some comments. Firstly, I do not have much respect for people who speak with great
confidence of how the population and its needs will develop over the next 100 years.
Everything can change in this time.
On the other hand, I believe that from what you said, with a scientific approach, it is
possible to ascertain some things which will apply, even at that time. That is, we can
tackle some of the fundamental things.
It may sound far from social aspects, but I can guarantee that Newtons laws will
also apply in the year 2100; thermodynamics will also apply. Induction over many years
make it safe enough for me to make these predictions. Are there corresponding social,
economic, and legal rules that we can be just as certain about in 100 years? I do not
think so.
No one has made this analysis, and it would be extremely interesting to do so. If it was
prepared and published, the author would be criticised immediately, as it is an incredibly
complicated task. I have no solutions, but you hinted at the appropriate direction in your
question.
Peder Andersen
Head of Secretariat, the Economic Council
When economists meet non-economists, it is hard to accept the fact that environmental
benefits can also be considered as consumption benefits, benefits to investment, or
frameworks for production. My point of departure therefore, is that the environment should
be perceived as a benefit or a framework for future consumption, investment, and
production opportunities.
It will also surprise some that economic theory supports the view that it is important to
take care. Application of economic theory in this connection corresponds to what we say to
our children when they ride their bikes. "Watch out when you cycle in traffic. Leave
in good time and cycle slowly because you dont know the way." When they come
home and say, " that was no problem, it was easy to find the way, and there were
traffic lights at all the junctions", then we can say, "OK, then you can go a
little later next time and cycle a little faster".
A corresponding balance is the point in economics. By cycling slower when we approach
something unknown there is a price because we do not advance quickly, and because we are
perhaps a little bored on the way. However, we create/buy greater security at the same
time. This balance can be explained more precisely using economic terms and
considerations.
An economists view of the precautionary principle is that it states the fact that
when a decision is to be made, account must be taken of the extent and nature of risk and
uncertainty. That is, risk must be included, and risk must be distinguished from
uncertainty.
Account must also be taken of risk aversion, that one is a little careful because one does
not want to just apply average consideration or an almost deterministic model. In
addition, account must be taken of the conditions connected with sustainability, namely
distributing resources between generations.
I do not wish to address the whole discussion on strong and weak sustainability, but I
will just emphasise that there are four factors (risk, uncertainty, risk aversion, and
distribution between generations) which must be considered when balancing or setting
priorities for costs and benefits.
The answer to the question, "is economic theory relevant to the precautionary
principle?", is, "yes". Why? Because economists know a lot about actuarial
theory and option theory, i.e. how to establish future possibilities. They know a lot
about portfolio theory, that is how to put a number of options together. Finally, they
also know something about sequential decision-making, and I would like to talk about this
in a little more detail.
Some believe that if, in some way, one has perfect knowledge, not so that the world
becomes deterministic, but that one has a distribution of probabilities which are known,
then one can merely apply normal deterministic models. But this is not certain. By being
cautious, one buys an option, a future possibility, from which one will be able to
benefit.
The fundamental idea in applying the precautionary principle is to increase possible
future choices. Everyone also knows that if we wish to increase these, then there is a
cost. When we buy insurance, we pay a premium, but what do we get? In fact we increase our
future choices because we insure against accidents, and others are willing to take on this
risk.
Can rational decisions can be made based on the precautionary principle, without applying
economic theory and methods? The answer is "no". I will only talk about the
theory, but of course the methodology is also relevant in implementation. The fundamental
environmental-economic model can be used as a starting point. In the deterministic simple
one-period model, the marginal damage from contamination (F), and the marginal cost of
reducing contamination, can be reproduced (see figure 12). That is, the more we wish to
reduce the contamination, the more expensive it will become, marginally. Economists focus
on optimal contamination, Foptimal (the intersection). At this point marginal damage and
marginal cost in preventing the damage are the same. With this model the precautionary
principle can be discussed in other situations.
The next figure, (see figure 13) can be read in the following way. The figure resembles
the previous figure. However, now we have: expected marginal damage, the best estimate of
the damage, given current knowledge. Suppose we now have a known probability distribution
for the damage, in this way we can find the expected value. The distribution is drawn in a
three-dimensional space. Optimal contamination under risk-neutrality for a rational
decision-maker will be at point F*, corresponding to contamination with complete
certainty.
And why is this? Because, for the rational decision-maker, with no risk aversion, the
rational choice will be the choice which maximises welfare. Risk-neutrality is often the
case because there are thousands of decisions for society to take, and in the long term
they counter balance each other. This is perhaps not true for the individual, who can go
bankrupt, For the State, which must take many decisions, however, it will be rational in
the long term to apply expected values if there are sufficiently many projects.
If there is already some form of risk aversion, the precautionary principle will be
manifested in that one will take out insurance. That is, one will avoid the difference
between the cost of reducing contamination and marginal damage becoming very big. The
model is designed so that it covers 90 per cent of the probabilities, but there is also a
five per cent risk of things getting even worse. So, the optimal decision will be to place
oneself somewhere to the left. How far to the left of F* this is, depends on how
risk-averse one is.
In addition to this there is the situation where one takes account of future generations
by giving them options. This will pull us further in the same direction. This is straight
from the text books. It is a quite simple theoretical method of interpreting the
precautionary principle in economic theory.
The next problem is uncertainty (see figure 14). In this case we cannot set a probability
distribution, even with expert knowledge. Uncertainty has many different aspects. It can
be yes/no, i.e. things will go completely wrong, or nothing will happen. Here
we can perhaps set probabilities, but if so, they are probabilities which can very quickly
change with new knowledge.
The figure shows a simple model: marginal damage is known up to a given point,
(F)threshold, but to the right of this point we do not know what happens. Things can go
completely wrong and damage can be very extensive. For purely pedagogical reasons I am
only discussing uncertainty of damage.
If things go completely wrong, then the function goes up vertically. As shown on the
model, it is assumed that marginal damage does not fall at the same time as contamination
increases. However, this can in fact be the case, for example, if a lake and stream are
already lifeless, it does not matter much if more contamination occurs.
Figure 12
Figure 13
Figure 14
We have therefore the curve marginal threshold cost, and if we have this picture, it is
not easy to see more than that the precautionary principle will draw us towards the
threshold value.
If we imagine that new knowledge becomes available, the (F)threshold value moves. If we
apply the precautionary principle according to the threshold value, but at the same time
intensify research, it is possible that we will obtain important new knowledge. For
example it can appear that it is better to contaminate a little over the threshold value,
a completely absurd idea for non-economists, that it could be good to pollute more. This
is because non-economists forget to think about the pleasure involved in activities which
in fact create pollution, at the same time as the damage now appears to be less that at
first assumed.
What is important here is sequential decision-making. If it is possible to obtain new
knowledge in the future, there is in fact something to be said for being careful now,
while investing in new knowledge. This is also the reason that some economists say that in
a number of areas it is better to search for new knowledge rather that spend money on
combating pollution.
The important thing about protection is to create options. At society level this means
that society must ensure options by making regulations today, but the other important
thing is that when new knowledge comes, it does not necessarily follow that environmental
regulations must be tightened. It could very easy follow, that on the basis of new
knowledge we can relax environmental regulations.
This presentation has been extremely brief, and the form of the presentation has not been
entirely loyal to the text books or journals. However, I believe that I have outlined some
central elements which provide a foundation for understanding the following main
principles.
There is thus recommendation that when we set some goals, we must at least try to
identify what they cost. In fact there are some economic models, including some general
models of equilibrium which can be applied. In the Economic Council we have tried to
calculate the costs of CO2 goals.
My answer to the question which was raised in connection with my talk must be, use as much
factual knowledge as possible. Use of knowledge reduces social-economic loss. Increased
use of the precautionary principle is for the common good, free for the individual, but
not without a social-economic price. We must recognise that increased demand for certainty
means higher taxes and/or reductions in other public services. We must make priorities.
There is imperfect natural-scientific and social-scientific knowledge of the cost-benefit
analysis, but we cannot justify writing off such analyses. We must concentrate more on
producing knowledge and methods. Therefore, basic environmental-economic research should
be offered higher priority.
Jesper Hermansen, Danish Environmental Protection Agency
It is interesting how in practice one can make cost-benefit analyses when
addressing some narrow risk balances. You did not say so much about this, apart from that
there is still a great lack of social and economic knowledge on this point.
It is very interesting for further discussion of the precautionary principle to decide,
what is the state of the art of using economic methods in assessments? When, as an
authority, we must make decisions, what are the social-economic consequences of either
making a decision, or not making a decision? How do you assess the current situation, and
what do you think the trends are in this discipline?
Peter Andersen
I fully recognise that it is not easy the make benefit calculations, that is,
attempt to put monetary values on the benefits of reducing contamination or uncertainty.
On the other hand, on the cost side I believe that for far too many years the authorities
have tried to calculate costs based on the costs of fulfilling these things.
Last Monday, there was a discussion in the Ministry of Finance on the environment and
environmental assessment in the Finance Act. It is my opinion that we can come a long way
towards putting figures on the cost of fulfilling some specific environmental objectives
in the same way as we can put figures on so much else we invest in or decide on in
society.
On the benefit side, we are moving into the same world when we must look at what the
social benefits actually are of treating people in hospital. We can easily do this by
considering the value of death. We can calculate what a death costs using some specific
methods. There is no one who will accept this, but the simple method is to say what does
the persons loss mean to future production? In addition there is the question of
what the person himself would have paid to avoid death.
This is also unacceptable for two reasons. Firstly, it does not place sufficient emphasis
on the future because this is not part of demand. We must say that we ourselves are
willing to do a lot in order to get him to do something. Secondly, it is unacceptable
because income distribution plays a far too important role.
Cost-benefit analyses are justifiably ridiculed when we see some important recreation
areas destroyed to make way for golf courses. A cost-benefit analysis can simply show what
is rational because golf players have greater incomes than others. Demand for a free area
to be converted to a golf course is greater than demand to make it normal parkland for
people to walk in because, in contrast to a golf course, it is difficult to issue tickets
as there is no entry price.
So, I am entirely in agreement that we will never reach home in this area. But, instead of
jumping into very advanced things on the benefit side, I think that the first step is to
try to use expertise to present some cost calculations and leave the rest to the political
process.
There are a number of American and other studies where in various ways there are attempts
to calculate the benefit of these things, and I do not underestimate their theoretical
foundation. I am merely very doubtful about their practical application. There are such
things as peoples willingness to visit and be close to recreational areas.
The questionnaire technique is what I most believe in, where in some sort of sneaky way we
find out about peoples willingness to pay. I would just like to repeat that if we
all consider these things as free benefits, then demand for them will be much greater than
it would be socially rational to supply. We can promote popular awareness of these things,
if it is done in an appropriate way, but I do not believe in a referendum on them.
Peter Skov, Confederation of Danish Industries
I entirely agree with considerations of the cost side, but if we look at the
benefits, you only mentioned the environmental benefits, and not those connected with
using a substance, a product, or in your own example, a car.
So, my question is, when you calculate benefits, is it just as difficult to calculate the
value of walking in the forest as to calculate the benefits of driving a car?
Peder Andersen
This must be attributed to my lack of precision. The overhead on marginal costs
by reducing benefits contains what you are looking for. You say that by reducing pollution
we must take measures which can either cost something, in the form of pure clean-up costs,
changes in production, changes in consumption, etc. However, you are right that they are
not all equally easy. Pure clean-up costs are very easy. But most will suggest that
activities are not in the form of cleaning up, but rather preventive or protective
activities.
Peter Skov
Some of the benefits we are speaking about are almost as intangible and
idealistic as the benefits of a better environment.
Peder Andersen
You mean that some of the costs to be put into the formula can be just a
difficult as the benefits? This is true. We have a mass of studies, for example on
traffic, which to some extent or other are based on travelling time.
Take all the cost-benefit analyses and other analyses which have been made on the Great
Belt bridge. Reduced travelling time is included in these, and one can use hourly salary
after tax, or the price of leisure time, or other factors, but there are many other
situations where we have a reasonable idea what people are willing to pay for time. A
number of studies have been made to explain the demand for dishwashers by time saved. Here
there are some good examples of what peoples time is worth. Or time at the limits
when people scream and shout if child-care facilities close half-an-hour earlier.
But I agree, and therefore my final overhead showed that in Denmark we are poorly equipped
in this regard, so the concept of utilisation-oriented environment and economy is weak
against other arguments which are not quite as scientifically well-based.
[Front page] [Contents] [Previous] [Next] [Top] |